Skip to main content

Imperfect Volitions


My name is Alexandre Billon. I am an Associate Professor in Philosophy at the University of Lille III. My research specialty is philosophical psychopathology, that is, the use of psychopathology to solve perennial philosophical riddles.

In a paper recently published in the Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, I argue that in order to be happier, people with desires like us must behave irrationally. This might seem plainly paradoxical: being happier is, other things being equal, being better off. Behaving irrationally is not doing what is best for me. How can I be made better off by not doing what is better for me?

Before debunking this paradox let me briefly present my argument. Many philosophers, thinkers and even religions have claimed that unfulfilled desires diminish our level of happiness. This, I believe is not quite right. There are two kinds of interesting counterexamples.

Some desires, first, positively contribute to please us before they are fulfilled. Future lovers can willingly prolong their flirting period, enjoying the obstacles that separate their desire to love and be loved from its foresighted satisfaction. Similarly, even though I desire to win the marathon, I take so much pleasure in the activities involved in this performance that my happiness is not decreased by the fact that I have not yet won the marathon. In these examples, the subject adopts a specific attitude towards her unfulfilled desires (call it erotic or lusory) that allows her to take pleasure in the mere contemplation of the desire’s possible satisfaction and in the activities involved in satisfying it.

Another counter-example to the claim that unulfilled desires diminish our level of happiness involves what we might call mourning attitudes. It is a common observation that important and irremediable losses can have little impact on one’s happiness. Persons losing their dearest relatives can rapidly adapt to their new situation. Even in the early phases of mourning, and despite their obvious sadness, some subjects report feeling happy “in the depths of their soul.” Less anecdotally, victims of disabling injuries or chronic illnesses tend to quickly return close to their former happiness “set-point.”

This general phenomenon of “hedonic adaptation” or “hedonic treadmill” has been extensively studied in the last twenty years and it has been confirmed by different measures. It is tempting to explain hedonic adaptation as a form of conative adaptation: The subjects would maintain their levels of happiness by giving up those desires whose fulfillment is thwarted by their losses. It is seldom noted, however, that this explanation has been empirically refuted. People thus maintain very strong desires to regain their healthy state even when they have hedonically adapted to their chronic illness or their disability. What happens is not that they give up their desire for health but rather that they adopt a certain mourning attitude towards it, allowing them not to be upset by its unsatisfaction.

So unfulfilled desires do not always decrease one’s happiness. We can adopt certain atttudes allowing us to remain happy in the face of unfulfille desires. There is however a price to pay for this. Someone who is not upset by an unfulfilled desire will not do her best to fulfill it, which is, I argue, generally irrational. The marathon is a case in point: the more you are serious about winning the marathon—suppose your career as a profesional runner depends on it— the less playful, the more upset you will be by your desire’s unsatisfaction. This will certainly help you satisfy your desire to win, but it will tend to make you less happy. In the paper I argue that this is a very general phenomenon, which can be explained by well established psychological law connecting the intensity of noxious stimuli, anxiety or punishment on the one hand, and learning or performance on the other hand: the Yerkes Dodson-Law. This law implies, I argue, that we won’t do our best to satisfy a desire—as we rationally should— unless its being unsatified decreases our level of happiness.

What about the paradox? How can one be made better off (happier) by not doing what is best for him (not doing one’s best to satisfy her desires)? This can happen, very simply, if the world rewards irrationality. Imagine that a whimsical god rewards me each time I do something stupid, like throwing  away money to become richer, or try to kill my son because I love him. With such a god, it would be better for me to become irrational. My claim is simply that because of the Yerkes-Dodson law, the world indeed acts as such a whimsical god, rewarding some forms of irrationality.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...