Skip to main content

Art and Belief

This post is by Ema Sullivan-Bissett, Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Birmingham, and previous Research Fellow on Project PERFECT.




Together with Helen Bradley and Paul Noordhof, I have edited a collection Art and Belief, recently published with Oxford University Press. The volume consists of twelve new essays at the intersection of philosophy of mind and art.

Our appreciation of artworks raises substantial challenges for our understanding of the cognitive attitudes involved, specifically, beliefs and related attitudes. Some of our beliefs concern the quality of the work in question. Others will derive from the content of the work, reflecting the commonly held view of art as a source of truth and knowledge. Both kinds of belief bring challenges for orthodox understandings of belief.

The volume is divided into four sections which explore a variety of questions on art and the nature of belief.

Section I: Author Testimony

Can we form justified beliefs upon author testimony? Kathleen Stock (‘Fiction, Testimony, Belief, and History’) argues that authors of fiction can pass on matters of empirical fact, and that there are no special problems with the testimony of authors of fiction.

Also optimistic about testimony in fiction is Eva-Maria Konrad (‘Signposts of Factuality: On Genuine Assertions in Fictional Literature’), who argues that a fictional text can consist of both fictional and factual discourse, with the latter being reliable sources of knowledge. 

In contrast, Anna Ichino and Gregory Currie (‘Truth and Trust in Fiction’), conceive of testimony as the highest point on what they call the expression spectrum, and argue that the expression of belief in fiction is usually below such a point, and as such fiction falls short of being a case of genuine testimony.

Section II: Non-Testimonial Epistemic Contributions of Fictions

If a work is one of fiction, it might be thought that it has no epistemic role to play. The second section of the book includes authors arguing for broadly positive conclusions about the epistemic value of fiction. James O. Young (‘Literary Fiction and True Beliefs’) claims that justified beliefs can be gained from fiction in virtue of its ability to present to readers perspectives on the world which they can adopt.

Peter Lamarque (‘Belief, Thought, and Literature’) focuses on the relationship between fiction’s epistemic contribution and its literary value. He argues that whatever epistemic contribution fiction makes, it is not relevant when we are thinking about fiction from a literary point of view. 

Allan Hazlett (‘Imagination that Amounts to Knowledge from Fiction’), argues for a new process of knowledge acquisition resulting from engaging in fiction. Taking fictions as invitations to imagine, he argues that imaginings engendered by fiction can amount to knowledge, regardless of whether this is consistent with the idea that a necessary condition on knowledge is belief. 

Lucy O’Brien (‘The Novel as a Source for Self-Knowledge’) closes this section of the book, arguing that although it is difficult for novels to transmit truths to readers directly, they can provoke in their readers reactions which constitute evidence for beliefs about the self.

Section III: Belief, Truth, and Attitudes from Fictional Persuasion

Studies of fictional persuasion seem to show that subjects’ real world beliefs change when they engage with fiction, but the beliefs gained are unstable, unjustified, and unreliable. These features might suggest that attitudes gained from fictional persuasion speak to (or perhaps against) the claim that beliefs are aimed at truth. Lisa Bortolotti and I (‘Fictional Persuasion, Transparency, and the Aim of Belief’) argue that a biological account of the connection between belief and truth is unthreatened by the findings from fictional persuasion, but that teleological accounts of the aim of belief (those in which the believer herself aims at truth in forming beliefs) are untenable in light of such findings.

In his paper (‘Fictional Persuasion and the Nature of Belief’), Asbjørn Steglich-Petersen focuses primarily on arguing for the compatibility of fictional persuasion with truth as the biological function for belief. In addition, he responds to mine and Lisa’s argument against the teleological account. Finally, Wesley Buckwalter and Katherine Tullman (‘The Genuine Attitude View of Fictional Belief’) argue for a doxastic reading of attitudes from fiction. They offer several objections to the non-doxastic view based on behavioural outputs of attitudes from fiction, the functional role of belief, and neuroscientific evidence.

Section IV: Aesthetic Appreciation and Belief

In the final section of the book, two authors explore the relationship between art and testimony, specifically, addressing the question of whether testimony is a legitimate source of aesthetic judgement. Jon Robson (‘Against Aesthetic Exceptionalism’) argues against a position which has it that aesthetic judgements are beliefs, and that these judgements cannot legitimately be formed on the basis of aesthetic testimony because they are subject to additional norms. He argues that pessimism about aesthetic testimony is untenable since it is in tension with various accounts of the nature of belief, and drives an unjustified line between aesthetic beliefs and other beliefs.

Daniel Whiting (‘Don’t Take My Word for It: On Beliefs, Affects, Reasons, Values, Rationality, and Aesthetic Testimony’) closes this section, and the volume, arguing that it is not possible to acquire aesthetic knowledge (or even rational aesthetic belief) from testimony alone. In arguing for this view, Whiting considers the way in which belief in the value of a work is supposed to serve as a causal and rational basis for affective responses to it.

Issues regarding the proper classification of mental states, how this relates to the role they play, as well as the way in which they are ideally generated, are ones of interest to philosophers of art and philosophers of mind. The interaction of philosophers working in aesthetics and mind is apt to lead to developments on these issues. Our hope is that this volume makes attractive such continuing interaction.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph