Skip to main content

Thought Insertion and the Minimal Self

Caitrin Donovan
I am a student in the Unit for the History and Philosophy of Science at the University of Sydney. In my recently completed honours dissertation, I argued that the delusional phenomenon of thought insertion problematises certain aspects of the 'minimal model' of self.

Many philosophers now believe that the self is in some way constructed by narrative; through socio-linguistically mediated story-telling, we achieve diachronic unity by taking a reflective stance on our experiences. According to the strong formulation of this thesis, conscious beings only develop selves once they acquire the higher-order linguistic and reflective capacities required for autobiographical self-understanding. 

Against this claim, Shaun Gallagher and Dan Zahavi argue that our capacity for narrative construction is prefigured and underpinned by a more basic form of self-awareness. Our experiences do not initially manifest as a sequence of anonymous events, only for us to subsequently reconcile them as our own via autobiographical thematisation. While autobiography may scaffold experiences and connect them over time, our stream of consciousness possesses an in-built, pre-linguistic and pre-reflective unity that the authors call the ‘minimal self’.

Gallagher and Zahavi’s formulation of the minimal model is premised upon a phenomenological account of self-consciousness, which involves a commitment to what we might call the ‘reflexivity thesis’. According to this thesis, subjectivity is not a dissociable aspect of our mental lives, but a transcendental pre-condition for all conscious experience. Consciousness always, and without exception, implies a tacit form of self-consciousness.

An implication of the reflexivity thesis is that it is not possible for a person to be aware of a given thought without at the same time being tacitly aware that it is their thought. All our occurent experiences are furnished with what Gallagher and Zahavi call a pre-reflective sense of ownership or mineness in virtue of which we are able to immediately recognise them as our own.

If the reflexivity thesis is true, and all our thoughts are self-intimating in this manner, then how do we make sense of the phenomenon of thought insertion? Patients experiencing the symptom report that they are introspectively aware of a thought ‘inside their mind’ that is not their own, most commonly asserting that it has been put there by another agent or external force (Rachel Gunn provides some excellent examples of patient reports in her blog post here).

Gallagher and Zahavi’s answer to this question is that subjects do not, in fact, deny ownership for their thought. What sufferers really mean by ‘they are not my thoughts’ is ‘I am not the agent of the thought’ or ‘I did not intentionally bring this thought about’. By striking this distinction between agency and ownership, Gallagher and Zahavi are able to defend the phenomenological theory of self-consciousness at the heart of the minimal model.

I side with theorists such as Bortolotti and Broome, Billon and Martin and Pacherie in arguing that the agency-based approach suffers from some fairly damning inadequacies. Perhaps the most significant problem is that citing an abnormal sense of agency does not help us distinguish thought insertion from the non-pathological and mundane experience of having an unbidden thought.

But prior to explanatory issues, it is not clear why we should interpret patients as merely denying agency for thoughts, as opposed to taking them at face value as denying ownership. The reasons Gallagher and Zahavi provide for rejecting an ownership-based interpretation are unsatisfactory and ultimately question-begging; without first assuming that awareness and self-awareness are inseparable, we have little reason to suppose, as proponents of the agency-based account do, that subjects with thought insertion are equivocating.

Insofar as subjects with thought insertion lack a sense of ownership for some of their thoughts, the reflexivity thesis is too strong a characterisation of the relationship between awareness and self-awareness. While Gallagher and Zahavi’s notion of a pre-reflective sense of self is salient, I contend that in order to properly characterise the anomalous experience of those afflicted with thought insertion, the robustness of the minimal self must not be over-exaggerated.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph