Skip to main content

Explaining Delusions (4)

This is a response to Phil Corlett's contribution to the blog, posted on behalf of Max Coltheart.


Max Coltheart
I think it would be helpful if at this stage the distinction between monothematic and polythematic delusions were introduced. A monothematic delusional condition is one where the patient has only a single delusional belief (or a small set of delusional beliefs related to a single theme). A polythematic delusional condition is one where the patient has many different and unrelated delusional beliefs. This distinction between monothematic and polythematic delusion was offered by Davies, Coltheart, Langdon and Breen (2001) and has been discussed by the philosopher Jennifer Radden in her book (Radden, 2010).


As Coltheart (2013) noted “Well-known cases of polythematic delusion include Daniel Schreber, a judge in the German Supreme Court, who believed that he had the plague, that his brain was softening, that divine forces were preparing him for a sexual union with God, and that this would create a new race of humans who would restore the world to a lost state of blessedness (Bell 2003); more details of his case are provided on pp. 50-52 of Radden’s book. Another example was the Nobel laureate John Nash (who was diagnosed with schizophrenia); among the delusional beliefs he held were that he would become Emperor of Antarctica, that he was the left foot of God on Earth, and that his name was really Johann von Nassau (Capps 2004).”
Forms of monothematic delusion include Capgras delusion (“My wife has been replaced by an impostor”), Cotard delusion (“I am dead”), Fregoli delusion (“People I know are following me around, but in disguise, so I can never recognize them”), mirrored-self misidentification ("The person I see when I look in the mirror isn’t me, but some stranger who looks like me”, the delusion of alien control (“Other people can cause my limbs to move without my intending them to move”), anosognosia (“My left arm is not paralysed”, when the patient’s armactually is paralysed) and somatoparaphrenia (“This isn’t my arm, it is my aunt’s”; here the patient is referring to her own arm).

In various papers on our two-factor account of delusional belief, we have raised the question of the scope of our account. We commit ourselves to the position that ouraccount is meant to apply to every form of monothematic delusion. This requires us to propose what Factor 1 is for each of the delusions mentioned above. Since Factor 1 is what determines the content of a monothematic delusion, and since the content of a monothematic delusion differs from delusion to delusion, Factor 1 will differ from delusion to delusion; in contrast, Factor 2 (impaired belief evaluation) is the same for all forms of monothematic delusion. We have taken the position that whether the two-factor account of delusional belief also offers a plausible account of polythematic delusion remains an open question, difficult to resolve at present because the kinds of detailed single-case studies that have been done with patients with monothematic delusions to yield data to which the two-factor theory canbe applied have simply not been done with cases ofpolythematic delusion.

Phil, is your work on delusion intended to apply both topolythematic delusions and also to the monothematic delusions I mention above?

Now to respond to your questions:

Q: “If prediction error is intact in people with delusions . . .”.

A: I did not understand what’s meant here by prediction error being intact. But in any case in my first response I pointed out that in our 2-factor account the occurrence ofprediction errors are crucial for the genesis of delusion. The role of Factor 1 in delusion is, precisely, that it causes prediction error (e.g. in Capgras delusion, the prediction that when I see my wife’s face there will be a response by my autonomic nervous system is erroneous). What remains intact here is the system that detects prediction errors and also the normal response to the detection of such errors, this normal response being what Phil terms “new learning” and what we term “belief system updating”. There is of course, in a person with a monothematic delusion, a second cognitive system that is not intact, the belief evaluation system: impairment of that system is our Factor 2.

Q: According to your answer, prediction error is neither factor 1 nor factor 2 but the interaction between them.

A: No, that isn’t what I said. As explained in my response to the question above, prediction error is caused by Factor 1.That is not the same thing as saying that prediction error is factor 1. If I have a stroke one night that disconnects my face recognition system from my autonomic nervous system, that is factor 1 re the Capgras delusion. But a prediction error will not occur at that time. It won’t occur until I next see the face of someone very close to me: my prediction of an autonomic response will now be erroneous here. In order for future encounters with my wife not to generate prediction error, I have to adopt the belief that the person with this face is not my wife, but some stranger. Once I have that belief, I will (correctly) predict no autonomic response when I see this face, thus achieving the goal that all of us always have: minimization of prediction error (see my comment on Jakob Hohwy’s Imperfect Cognitions post about his book “The Predictive Mind”).

Q: According to this explanation, belief formation is intact in your model – the imposter hypothesis is appropriate given the perceptual experience, and that candidate is adopted and then never updated? Is that correct?

A: Yes, that’s correct – that’s what the 2-factor account says about Capgras delusion. With the qualification that it seems that tactful CBT-style conversation about the delusional belief might sometimes lead to temporary doubts about the delusional belief: see Coltheart (2007, pp. 1053-1054) for a verbatim transcription of one such conversation with a Capgras patient.

Q: Do the patients with perceptual disruption but no delusions (critical to 2-factor theory) have normal genesis of candidate explanations also? So the imposter explanation crosses their mind but they discount it?

A: Yes, that’s the simplest position we can take, so we take it given that there is nothing to rule it out. These patients are able to discount the explanation because of the intactness of their belief evaluation systems (i.e. the absence of Factor 2). So we don’t need the third factor of which you spoke.


References

Bell, D. 2003: Paranoia. Cambridge, UK: Icon

Capps D. 2004. John Nash’s delusional decade: a case of paranoid schizophrenia. Pastoral Psychology, 52, 193–218

Coltheart, M. (2013). On the distinction between monothematic and polythematic delusions: Some comments on On Delusion (Radden, 2011). Mind & Language, 28, 103-112.

Davies, M., Coltheart, M, Langdon, R. and Breen, N. 2001: Monothematic delusions: Toward a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 8, 133-158.

Radden, J. (2011): On Delusion. London: Routledge.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph