Skip to main content

Explaining Delusional Belief: The Two-Factor Account

Max Coltheart
I'm Max Coltheart, Emeritus Professor of Cognitive Science at the Centre for Cognition and its Disorders and Department of Cognitive Science, at Macquarie University. I work in cognitive neuropsychology (especially developmental dyslexia) and cognitive neuropsychiatry (especially delusional belief). I am also interested in the use of functional neuroimaging to attempt to test cognitive theories. I did a joint undergraduate degree in psychology and philosophy at the University of Sydney and have worked with the philosophers Martin Davies, John Sutton and Peter Menzies.

Since the late 1990s my colleague Robyn Langdon and I, initially in collaboration with Martin Davies and the clinical neuropsychologist Nora Breen, and later in collaboration with various others especially Ryan McKay, have been developing a cognitive-level theory of the genesis of delusions which we call the two-factor theory. Our view is that scientific understanding of any delusional condition has been achieved if the answers to two questions has been discovered. Question 1 is: what caused the idea that is the content of the delusion to first come to the deluded person’s mind? Question 2 is: what caused this idea – a candidate for belief - to be accepted as a belief, rather than rejected, which is what ought to have happened because there is so much evidence against it?

Our theory stems from ideas about delusion put forward by William James in 1890 and Brendan Maher in 1974. Both proposed that delusional beliefs result from the use of intact normal reasoning processes in an attempt to develop hypotheses to explain abnormal experiences that the patient is having. These abnormal experiences correspond to factor 1 in our theory, and we agree with James and Maher that it is the application of normal processes of inference (we suggest it is abductive inference that is used here) that yield the hypotheses that can become delusional beliefs.

Where we depart from James and Maher is in our view that the hypotheses abductively inferred from the abnormal experiences as attempted explanations of these experiences will normally be evaluated, and then rejected because of the strength of the evidence against them. That would prevent these candidates for belief from becoming actual (delusional) beliefs. Only if a second factor is also present, an impairment of the belief evaluation system, will patients fail to reject the hypotheses suggested by the abnormal experiences. So only when this second factor is present will delusional beliefs arise. (See Coltheart, Menzies, and Sutton 2009).

Consider the Capgras delusion: the belief that someone emotionally close to you, often a spouse, has been replaced by a complete stranger. Haydn Ellis, Andy Young and colleagues showed in 1997 that in patients with Capgras delusion their autonomic nervous systems do not respond much more strongly to familiar faces than to unfamiliar faces (much stronger response when a face is familiar is what is normally seen). So a patient expecting to have a strong autonomic response when he sees someone who looks exactly like his wife will not have this experience. What could explain this strange and unexpected (absence of) experience? Well, suppose that this person was not the wife but some complete stranger: that hypothesis would explain the absence of the experience. That’s how James or Maher would explain Capgras delusion using their one-factor theory. But this explanation can’t be correct, because patients with damage to ventromedial regions of frontal lobe also do not respond much more strongly to familiar faces than to unfamiliar faces; yet they are not delusional. They are able to avoid adopting as a belief the hypothesis “This is not my wife”. Capgras patients can’t avoid this, and we infer that this is the case because in the Capgras patients a second factor is present, an impairment of the normal processes of belief evaluation.

The general form of the analysis illustrated above is one we have applied to the explanation of a variety of delusions. It runs like this. First, ask Question 1 (what caused the idea that is the content of the delusion to first come to the deluded person’s mind?). Hope to identify such a potential cause. Then seek evidence from the neuropsychological literature for the existence of patients in whom precisely this cause is present but who are not delusional.  Then claim that what distinguishes the delusional from the nondelusional patients is that the delusional patients have a second impairment, an impairment of the belief evaluation system; this impairment prevents them from using evidence that would prevent them from accepting the belief, i.e. evidence that if used would prevent them from becoming delusional.

Some independent criterion that would support the claim that an impairment of the belief evaluation system characterises all patients with delusions is needed. One approach we have taken here is to point to various pieces of evidence suggesting an association between an impairment of the belief evaluation system and damage to the right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex.

But that’s for another blog post. And so is the topic of hypnotic induction of delusional belief: we work on that with Amanda Barnier, Rochelle Cox and their hypnosis research group.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...