Skip to main content

Explaining Delusions (1)

This is a response to Max Coltheart's post (and comments), posted on behalf of Phil Corlett.


Phil Corlett



As usual Max, a thorough, interesting and well written piece.

I am curious about a couple of things.

First, you say that the prediction error signal fails in our model. Are you implying that we believe delusions form in the absence of prediction error? Our data point to the opposite case. Prediction errors are inappropriately engaged in response to events that ought not to be surprising. That is why people with delusions learn about events (stimuli, thoughts, percepts) that those without delusions would ignore.

Second, you claim that prediction error is key to belief updating in your model. Are you aligning prediction error with Factor 1 or Factor 2? It seems Factor 1, but I wanted to check – particularly since you align Factor 2 with the functioning of right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, which, as you know, we’ve implicated in prediction error signaling with our functional imaging studies.

Third, I am curious about some specific facets of 2 Factor theory: It seems to me that your account is based on, and works well for what I call Neuropsychological delusions, delusions that arise form some sort of closed head injury damaging right frontal and parietal cortex amongst other regions. Your argument is clear, you need perceptual system damage (Factor 1) and belief evaluation damage (Factor 2). In these neuropsychological cases, doesn’t the damage happen simultaneously, as a result of a stroke or accident? If so, why do they update their old belief at all?

According to your model, you would need to wake up from your coma, have the experience of unfamiliarity for your wife, update your belief appropriately (using the normally functioning prediction error signal) then hold fast to your belief. To form the delusion based on the odd experience, wouldn’t you need belief evaluation to be working normally, then once the belief is formed, evaluation would break.
 
Fourth, why are these monothematic delusions so circumscribed? Belief evaluation seems rather circumscribed – they do not form delusions about numerous themes like patients with schizophrenia. Wouldn’t a general belief evaluation deficit require that?

Fifth, your model does not allow for any top-down influence of belief on perception. Visual illusions like the rotating hollow mask demonstrate the powerful effect that priors have on how we see the world. Your separate factors seem not to allow for that – would you agree?

Along these lines, spontaneous confabulation, where, after a head injury, people believe for example that they are still engaged in their pre-injury lives (e.g. a lawyer referring to the doctors and nurses in the hospital and judges and barristers), seems to be a more top-down delusion like phenomenon. What is the Factor 1 here?

Further more, Max asked whether there were any examples of people with pure Factor 1 damage who form delusions (as prediction error theory would demand). In the absence of a clearer definition of what Factor 1 is, I will assume that it would engender a pure sensory deficit. There is a case report of someone with damage to the brachial plexus, a key node of the peripheral nervous system supplying the arm and hand. After damaging his brachial plexus (and crucially in the absence of central damage) he began to feel that his hand had been replaced by a mechanical robot hand that did not belong to him and began to produce elaborate narratives to explain his experiences.

Finally, I would like to offer a consilient explanation that might unite our models.

 It is important to appreciate that there are at least two different types of prediction error. There is the standard, gradient descent or delta rule based prediction error that is employed to update weights in particular learning settings. I’ll call this within model prediction error, we use this to learn about the specific aspects of a model that we have assumed to pertain. There is also a prediction error over models – it tells us that the model we assumed is inadequate and we need to invoke another. Computational learning theorists like Nathaniel Daw have shown separable but interacting neural mechanisms for these errors – crucially, model or state prediction error is located in DLPFC and parietal cortex. Could prediction error be the algorithmic bases (Pace David Marr) for Factors 1 and 2?

Perhaps that is something to be developed in another blog post.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph