Skip to main content

Delusions as Acceptances

Richard Dub
My name is Richard Dub. I'm currently a postdoctoral fellow at the Swiss Centre for the Affective Sciences, and I recently received my Ph.D. in Philosophy from Rutgers University. In my dissertation, I offered a model of delusions that attempted to answer two questions: What are delusions? How are they formed? Delusions, I argue, are pathological acceptances formed on the basis of pathological cognitive feelings.

Neither 'acceptance' nor 'cognitive feeling' is an entirely mainstream concept.  A concern that motivates a lot of my work is that it is procrustean to try to explain all mental phenomena in terms of a select few propositional attitudes.  There is little reason to insist that belief and desire must take their traditional place of prominence.  The mind is lush, not sparse.  The ordinary concept of belief is likely what Ned Block calls a "mongrel concept": a concept that imperfectly picks out various dissimilar cognitive states.

Psychopathologies present us with cases that ordinary folk psychology, with lumpen terms like 'belief', is not well-equipped to describe.  They often reveal that mental states and processes which usually coincide can be dissociated from one another.  We might need to be revisionary with our ontology of mental states in order to capture these dissociations.

Delusions are a case in point.  Others on this blog have discussed how, because delusions act like such strange beliefs, they might well not be beliefs at all.  This is non-doxasticism.  But then, what would delusions be, if not beliefs?  Luckily, we don't need to introduce an ad hoc category.  An alternative notion---"acceptance"---can on occasion be spotted lurking throughout philosophy, used to explain phenomena as diverse as voluntary change of mind, self-deception, akrasia, pedagogy, and our understanding of myth and legend.  Frankish and Velleman have both suggested that acceptances can help explain delusions.  Delusions involve acceptance without belief.

It is easiest to get an grip on the type of acceptance at play in delusions (an imperfect grip, mind you) by considering acceptance as supposition without introspective insight.  Over the course of a dinner, we can suppose something for the sake of argument, and then have a discussion as if we believed it.  We usually have good introspective insight about when we are merely supposing something rather than believing it.  However, what would it look like if we lost this insight?  I claim that such a state would look an awful lot like a delusion (though there are differences---delusions are not usually formed voluntarily, for example).  In fact, it turns out that many more mundane "beliefs", such as personal, ideological, or religious convictions, also share these features.  Lisa Bortolotti has argued in her excellent book on delusions that non-doxasticism is threatened by the fact that delusions do not look very different from more mundane irrational beliefs.  But it is not threatened if these other irrational "beliefs" turn out not to be beliefs either.

In a future post, I'll discuss how these pathological acceptances are formed.  You can read more about my research interests on my webpage, and feel free to e-mail me with questions if interested.  Also be sure to take a look at my iconographic representations of various delusion types!

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...