Skip to main content

Art and Emotion: An Interview with Derek Matravers

In this post Matilde Aliffi, PhD student at the University of Birmingham, interviews Derek Matravers (pictured below), who is professor of philosophy at the Open University, and has interests in aesthetics and philosophy of art. Derek is the author of Fiction and Narrative (OUP, 2014) and has recently completed a book on empathy which will be published by Polity Press.



MA: You are a leading expert in aesthetics and philosophy of art. How did you become interested in these areas?

DM: There were three reasons for my interest. The first was that there were some really inspirational figures working in the area when I first went to University; in particular, Richard Wollheim who had been at UCL just before I arrived. Other greats, such as Bernard Williams, clearly had a keen interest in the topic even if they never wrote about (although Williams did write occasional pieces on opera, which have since been collected into a book). 

Secondly, it was a natural extension of my interest in art. When I started, I hoped it might lead me on the road to being an art critic, but it is probably just as well that it did not. 

Finally, there really are some very difficult problems in aesthetics. One way to think about it is that it has all the problems associated with meta-ethics and then some. There are problems of objectivity and realism, but also problems that stem from the centrality of perception. Nobody thinks that the canonical way to access the moral value (or disvalue) of (say) global inequality is by looking at it. However, that precisely is the canonical way to access the aesthetic value of (say) a Poussin or a Picasso. Why? And how can we get judgements that are binding on others from this basis? There is also something to be said for the view, which has pretty much died out at least in Anglo-American philosophy, that aesthetics is utterly central to philosophy – this view is core to the Scottish Enlightenment, Kantian and post-Kantian German philosophy, and others. This is because it really is about the way we are in the world.

MA: Do you think there is a difference between attitudes caused by fiction and attitudes caused by non-fiction?

DM: This is where I differ from most of my colleagues. It is tempting to think that the mental attitudes appropriate to fiction differ from those appropriate to non-fiction. The consensus seems to be something like this: when I read a newspaper, I believe the content of the paper and when I read a novel, I imagine the content of the novel. I think this is difficult to sustain. In essence, the problem is this. If we construe imagining as simulation (as most people writing in this area do), imagining stuff is equated with processing stuff ‘off line’. 

However, the content of what we process ‘off line’ is neutral between fiction and non-fiction. All simulation amounts to is processing stuff that is not coming in via perception and coming out via action. So by this account of imagining we imagine both fictions and non-fictions. OK, you might say, but surely the mental state appropriate to non-fiction is linked to belief in the way that the mental state appropriate to fiction is not. Again, it is not so clear. There are plenty of propositions in non-fiction that do not merit belief, and plenty of propositions in fiction that do merit belief. 

A better way of looking at the matter is to realise that we all need to represent the content of a narrative to ourselves, whether it is fiction and non-fiction. Hence, we get some kind of mental model of its content. The propositions contained in that mental model may or may not be beliefs. Once we have said that, which applies both to fictions and non-fictions, it is not clear that there is much left to sort out.

MA: Does art express emotions?

DM: The relation between art and emotion is really difficult to get clear. Clearly, art can arouse all kinds of emotions: it can bore us, excite us, make us sad, happy, nostalgic, wistful, and many more besides. I think that, within this, we need to make quite a sharp distinction between two different sorts of case. 

The first sort of case is simple emotional arousal. This is not very philosophically interesting; lots of things (say) excite us, from ice-cream to downhill skiing and it would be surprising if works of art did not figure amongst the list. 



The second sort of case is when we want to say, not just that the works cause us to feel an emotion, but that the works of art *express* an emotion. In fact, we can judge that a work of art expresses an emotion without – apparently – our feeling any emotion at all. Somehow our experience contains the work of art, and the emotion, and it is not clear how the two are related. 

I think some of the most interesting theories at the moment are some variety of the thought that we imagine of the work of art that it is an expression of an emotion. If this works at all, it works for music but it is not clear how it generalises to other art forms. Maybe we need some variety of the thought that we experience the work as similar to the appearance of an emotion. Or maybe both. It is not given, after all, that the relation is the same in all cases.

MA: What are your current research interests?

DM: I have just finished a book on empathy, and am taking a new departure. Together with Helen Frowe, of the Stockholm Centre for the Ethics of War and Peace, we are trying to think through the implications of protecting what the UN calls ‘cultural property’ in war zones. It is a difficult and slightly depressing area; what are we prepared to pay in terms blood and treasure, to preserve objects of great aesthetic and cultural value? If the most effective way to drive ISIS out of Palmyra (say) is to bomb it, how should we think through the various issues involved?

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...