Skip to main content

The Epistemic Value of Emotions in Politics


Benedetta Romano is a doctoral candidate in the department of neurophilosophy and ethics of neuroscience at the Ludwig-Maximilians-University Munich. Her research centers on the philosophy of emotions, focusing on various topics, such as the epistemic relevance of political emotions, the capacity of emotions to establish a narrative connection, and their function in analogical reasoning. Moreover, she is interested in the emotional dimension of different issues in applied ethics, such as torture and immigration.


Do the emotions that we experience towards political issues, characters and events, provide us with any valuable knowledge about them? My answer is a resounding yes, and in in my paper, I articulate it as follows. First, I address the epistemic part of the question. I argue that emotions can provide some knowledge about their objects, including political ones, by generating and modifying beliefs about them, and that such knowledge is evaluative in character. But is this knowledge epistemically reliable?

Some have claimed that it is not, as emotions often lead to distorted and unwarranted beliefs. In response to this, I adopt a coherentist framework, suggesting that, although emotions in themselves are not sufficient to ground evaluative knowledge about political facts, they can do so together with other coherent epistemic attitudes about those facts. I address now the political part of the question: is the knowledge provided by emotions, politically relevant? 

First, I discuss the notion of political sophistication, and I argue that the latter includes not only factual knowledge about political issues (e.g. the name of the president), but also evaluative knowledge about them, that is, knowledge about how those political issues invoke our values (e.g. whether or not my values conform to the policies approved by the president). Then, by considering studies about the influence of emotions on political opinions, I argue that, although both more and less politically sophisticated individuals may experience emotions towards political issues, and use them in their evaluative judgments, the difference in their level of factual knowledge, makes the emotions experienced by the first more informative than those experienced by the latter.

From this, I conclude that the contribution of emotions to the evaluative knowledge about political objects, is conditional to the presence of an appropriate factual knowledge about those objects. Still, this does not clarify whether the contribution of emotions is actually relevant: even admitting that my emotional attitude towards D. J. Trump figures among the mental states grounding my opinion about him as being untrustworthy, is my emotion really necessary for reaching such an opinion?

By appealing to Goldie, I argue that there is a qualitative difference between the evaluative knowledge achieved with and without the contribution of emotions. In politics, I claim, the distinctive evaluative information disclosed by the emotions towards a political object, consists in the personal import of the latter for the agent: an emotional reaction towards a political object not only signals certain evaluative properties of the object, as they could be attributed to it without any emotional involvement, but it signals that the agent personally, with her values and beliefs, is sensitive to these properties. 

I argue that this distinctive contribution is relevant, not merely in virtue of its content, but because of its inclusion in the integrative process, aimed at reaching coherence, through which the agent’s evaluative knowledge is formed. By including the emotional component, in fact, the values and beliefs that the agent holds in relation to a certain political object, are confronted with their actual import for the agent in respect to the object. As a result, the opinion that the agent forms, is characterized as really invoking, and not just ideologically or superficially reflecting, her values and beliefs. This makes the agent’s evaluative knowledge more sophisticated, and it grounds, I believe, the epistemic relevance of emotions in the political context.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...