Skip to main content

Society for Applied Philosophy conference

In this post, I report from our applied epistemology panel at the Society for Applied Philosophy Annual Conference 2018, held in Utrecht from 29th June – 1st July.


When you think about typically ‘applied’ sub-disciplines of philosophy, epistemology might not be the first area of study to cross your mind. But Boudewijn de Bruin and Lisa Warenski, two speakers from last year’s panel on Applied Epistemology in the Professions decided that an applied epistemology panel should be a fixture of the SAP annual conference, and together with Anneli Jefferson and myself, put together a proposal, looking at deepening understanding of the application of the concept of epistemic injustice to topics in both mental health and finance for this year. (Unfortunately Lisa couldn’t make it on the day, so I report on just the three talks, but do keep an eye out for her work in this area!)


First Boudewijn explored epistemic injustice in consumer markets, starting from the observation that on some views of market forces and the relevant agents involved, increased competition ought to decrease discrimination – but this is not what we in fact observe: legislation, not competition, protects against discrimination. Boudewijn then outlined a number of areas where, despite the relevant civil rights acts, epistemic injustice crops up. 

There are two kinds of cases. First, there are those on the supply side, where, for instance, two customers with near enough identical business proposals apply for a loan, but a white customer’s application is favoured over that of a black customer. Then there are cases on the demand side, where customers do not even apply, due to having limited experience (which Boudewijn diagnosed as limited epistemic self-confidence) because of structural injustices and past interactions where their testimonies had not been afforded appropriate credibility in financial contexts. Boudewijn then discussed potential strategies to ameliorating these distinctly epistemic injustices, as well as their limitations.


Anneli moved the focus of the application of epistemic injustice to mental health contexts. She started from the idea that when we believe that a person is experiencing a mental health problem, this has a strong influence on the way we interpret what they say and how likely we are to believe them. These cases are different to epistemic injustice as it arises in the context of race or gender, because these categories are independent of the supposed features that underwrite epistemic injustice (assigning lower credibility to testimony). But the same is not necessarily true in mental health contexts (where, for instance, it may be epistemically justified to assign a lower level of credibility to a person for the reason that part of their experience is of, e.g., delusions or other inaccurate beliefs). 

The situation is complicated by the fact that, in many clinical interactions, there is incomplete information to determine the level of credibility that should be assigned to the person’s testimony. Anneli discussed how lack of research into differentiating the cases, as well as the risks of stigma and spurious diagnostic categories such as Borderline Personality Disorder, further complicate the issue.


I gave the final talk on the panel, thinking about epistemic injustice in the particular context of Alzheimer’s Disease (AD). One might think that a disease which is chiefly characterized by inevitable cognitive decline is a strange place to look for epistemic injustice risk. You might think that people with AD are in an epistemically poor position, but that’s a feature of the disease, not due to injustice. Indeed, I got into thinking about AD because of my work on confabulation, AD being one of the contexts in which confabulation occurs. 

But I’ve also been thinking about storying telling in non-clinical contexts, and how stories shape our perceptions of, and interactions with, the world. As such, the “cognitive decline” story tracks an important feature of AD, but if that’s the only story we tell, then we risk viewing AD patients as incapable of being any kind of knowers, when in fact much embodied knowledge (particularly around touch, movement and music) remains throughout the progression of the disease. 

I argued that withdrawing from embodied interactions with AD patients because we focus on cognitive decline risks putting them in an epistemically worse position, cutting them off from important bodily routines that facilitate knowledge of the self, the world, and their connections to loved ones. I think this is a form of epistemic injustice because the specifically epistemic losses above result from incomplete societal resources for understanding AD (e.g. excessive focus on cognitive decline, and lack of consideration of embodied knowledge in the stories we typically tell about AD). Telling better stories has the potential to ameliorate this risk.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph