Skip to main content

Thought Insertion and Immunity to Error of Misidentification

Matthew Parrott
On April 12, the University of Fribourg will be hosting a one-day workshop on delusions focusing on thought insertion. Gottfried Vosgerau (Dusseldorf) will be presenting a paper entitled 'Introspection and the Delusion of Thought Insertion' and I will be presenting an essay called 'Immunity to Error and the Experience of Thought Insertion'.

My essay examines the question of whether the phenomenon of thought insertion puts any pressure on the well-known principle that our first-personal way of knowing about thoughts rules out the possibility of misidentifying the subject of those thoughts. Prima facie, it seems that that a subject who reports an experience of thought insertion knows what she is thinking in a characteristically first-personal way but is wrong about who is thinking the thought (Campbell 1999). If this is right, then it suggests our ordinary first-person access to thoughts may not really be immune to errors of misidentification.

The underlying issue here is not just about the possibility of immunity to a certain kind of mistake but rather about the nature and structure of conscious experience. Immunity to error invites us to reflect on the structure of an experience of thought insertion, to understand what that experience is like. Is it structurally similar to more familiar experiences of thoughts or is it radically different and, if so, how? One reason it is important to get clear about the nature of a typical experience of thought insertion is that, as Jordi Fernandez has argued in his recent book, 'in order to understand why a subject with thought insertion has the kind of experience that she tries to express by saying things like "I have such-and-such a thought but it is not my thought", we first need to have some grasp of what the experience might be like.' (2013, pg. 147)

Many theoretical approaches claim that experiences of thought insertion are missing some feature that we find in ordinary experiences of thinking. For instance, it is often said that these experiences lack a 'sense of agency' (Stephens and Graham 2000; Carruthers 2012), or 'action-awareness' (Peacocke 2008), or the subject's endorsement of a thought content (Bortolotti and Broome 2009; Pickard 2010). What these all views suggest is that an experience of thought insertion is different in kind from an ordinary experience, that lacking some component makes it fundamentally different from ordinary experience.  

At the workshop, I'll propose that an experience of thought insertion is structurally identical to ordinary conscious experience; it is a state of awareness of oneself thinking a particular thought. Thus, rather than missing some element or feature found in ordinary conscious experience, I shall claim that the experience of thought insertion involves something more, a kind of phenomenological overlay that alienates the person from her state of awareness.

This proposal is analogous to the account developed by Ellis and Young (1990; cf. Stone and Young 1997) to explain the Capgras delusion (recently discussed by Max Coltheart on this blog) and I think it also fits very nicely with prediction error theory (i.e., the anomalous experiential overlay is plausibly thought of as an aberrant prediction error signal - also discussed by Max Coltheart and Phil Corlett).

Finally, I think the picture, unlike others, helps us understand why subjects of thought insertion often express ambivalence to their experiences of inserted thoughts.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...