Skip to main content

Workshop: Dreams, Delusions and Early Modern Literature

The workshop “Dreams, Delusions and Early Modern Literature” was held at University of Birmingham (3-4 April 2014). The workshop was organized by Ita Mac Carthy and it is a part of Balzan Prize project, ‘Literature as an Object of Knowledge‘. The aim of the workshop was to examine early modern literary texts that theorize the nature of dreams and delusions and describe individuals who fail to distinguish between what is real and unreal.

Although the workshop was mainly on literary studies, Phil Gerrans and I had the opportunity to give philosophical talks at the 'Cognitive Keywords Session'.

Gerrans, on the basis of this paper, talked about both delusion and dream. According to him, dream and delusion are in a sense similar phenomena, and the similarity consists in the fact both are caused by the abnormal functioning of reality-testing system. The reality-testing system is deactivated in dreams, while it is compromised in delusion. More precisely, so-called 'default mode network' is relatively disconnected from reality in delusion, and it is influenced by various cognitive biases in different levels.

In my talk, I argued that different understandings of the concepts 'belief' and 'rationality' have different implications for whether or not delusions are beliefs and whether or not delusions are significantly more irrational than healthy beliefs. For example, delusions might not be beliefs according to the causal functional concept of belief, but they might be beliefs according to the biological or teleological concept. Again, delusions might not be significantly more irrational than healthy beliefs according to the mathematical, Bayesian concept of rationality, but they might be significantly more irrational according to the biological or ecological concept of rationality.

Non-philosophical talks discussed a wide variety of texts including Orlando Furioso (Ariosto), An Essay on Criticism (Pope), Meditations (Descartes), D’Alembert’s Dream (Diderot), Letter from Thomas More to Erasmus, Tragiques (D'Aubigne). Dream and delusion arise in those texts in different ways, but what was particularly interesting to me is the fact that dream and delusion are sometimes described as useful or meaningful. In Orlando Furioso, for example, Orlando's delusion about Angelica seems to be playing a kind of psychological defence function. At the end of Meditation I, again, Descartes describes dream as the source of psychological comfort when the reality is not very pleasant. This is taken to be analogous with the fact that ordinary beliefs are very comfortable and being skeptical about them is not very pleasant.

The workshop was a great success, and convinced me that past literary works contain ideas that are still worth exploring. The question about the usefulness or meaning of delusion, for example, overlaps with the central questions of the epistemic innocence of imperfect cognition project here at Birmingham.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph