Skip to main content

Falsity Workshop


This post is by Anneli Jefferson, Research Fellow at the University of Birmingham, working on the Costs and Benefits of Optimism project.

On June 27th, Nils Kürbis and Dan Adams hosted a workshop on falsity entitled 'Falsity – Not just Truth’s Poor Relation' at Birkbeck (see picture of venue above). The lively workshop approached falsity in a number of thought-provoking ways.

Those of us who don’t work in metaphysics take the concept of falsity for granted. But once you start thinking about what falsity is, numerous puzzles arise. If you assert that something is false, in other words, it is not the case, what makes that claim true?

When we speak truly, we say how things are. If we speak falsely, things aren’t how we say they are. But doesn’t that mean that what we say is there is not there at all? So what are we talking about? It seems as if we are talking about nothing at all, so how can what we said even make sense? One response to this problem is that there are negative facts. But that’s puzzling too. A negative fact records the absence of a fact. But if there are negative facts, doesn’t that mean that absences exist? And if absences exist, shouldn’t they be presences, rather than absences?

Keith Hossack gave a spirited defence of negative facts: all false statements share a property; that the state of affairs expressed fails to obtain. The facts that make the statements false have the property of negativity in common. Just as fire engines, pillar boxes and roses share the property of redness, false statements share negativity.

Tuomas Tahko on the other hand argued that we should understand falsity in terms of a basic property of incompatibility. What is red is not green, because being red is incompatible with being green. This way we can explain away negativity in terms of only properties that things have and which properties are incompatible with each other.

In her talk, MM McCabe addressed arguments by the sophists in Plato’s Euthydemos. The sophists claim that they can teach anyone anything: precisely because there is a problem about believing false propositions, as there is nothing that could correspond to a false proposition, there is nothing to believe. So all our beliefs must be true, if meaningful, and disagreement is impossible. MM showed how the account Socrates puts forward in the dialogue allows for falsity and a normative conception of speaking and saying. Only by getting things wrong and being able to communicate about mistakes does learning become possible.

I asked about the role of falsity in positive illusions and optimistically biased beliefs. Are these biased beliefs about ourselves and our future actually false and do such false beliefs serve a purpose? As it turns out, whether positive illusions are false or not is frequently not a straightforward matter. A number of methodological, epistemological and even metaphysical problems arise when we try to assess whether a particularly rose-tinted belief is in fact false.

One familiar problem from the psychological literature is establishing which individuals have false, overly positive beliefs about themselves. Taking the example of the optimism bias: If our seemingly overly optimistic prediction came true, surely our belief was not false? We can maintain that these optimistically biased beliefs were false even when the event does end up occurring ,if we say that individuals err in their estimate of the likelihood of a positive event occurring. Needless to say, establishing the actual likelihood of an event occurring is a further challenge.

In discussing the question whether positive illusions have a purpose, I distinguished between a notion of purpose as a function specified by evolutionary theory and one which claims that positive illusions are good for us in some normative sense. I highlighted some examples of positive illusions where it is plausible that the false belief itself was evolutionarily beneficial but concluded that it was unclear whether unrealistically optimistic beliefs about the future have historically been beneficial to survival and reproduction. 

I argued that positive illusions are good for us when the positive effect they have on emotional well-being and outlook is not outweighed by the harms that can arise, both in terms of misguided action and as regards our ability to have a coherent, shared view of the world and ourselves. Lisa Bortolotti and I will be exploring these and other issues concerning unrealistic optimism further in our project on the optimism bias which started on the 1st September.

All talks received rigorous but sympathetic scrutiny both by a commentator and by the audience. Thanks to Nils and Dan for organizing an excellent workshop.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph