Skip to main content

‘Pathologizing Mind and Body’ Workshop in Leuven


What is the relation between mental disorders and physical disorders? Is it possible to find a biological basis for mental disorders? What purpose would a reduction of mental disorders to physical disorders serve? These are some of the questions addressed at the workshop ‘Pathologizing Mind and Body’ organized by Jonathan Sholl and Marcus Eronen. Philosophers, psychologists and psychiatrists approached this topic from different angles and highlighted problems and recent developments.

In the first talk, Ignaas Devish stressed the distinction between suffering and pain, claiming that suffering is not a phenomenon that is amenable to diagnostic operationalisation and medicalization. He argued that because of this, victims of traumatic events should be offered an ethical debriefing in addition to psychological debriefing, which allows them focus on their suffering and the existential problems they face from a non-medical perspective.

Arantza Exteberria talked about ‘Interactive Bioloops and Pathology’. She pointed out  that biolooping is a common phenomenon, with social levels thoroughly influencing biological levels of functioning. Because of this, there is no clear mental/physical distinction when it comes to pathologies. Furthermore, the complex and dynamic nature of individual-organism relations suggests that personalized medicine will be a fruitful way to proceed. 

Denny Borsboom introduced the audience to the network approach to mental disorders. Rather than searching for a unified cause that underlies a variety of pathological symptoms in a certain disorder, this model focuses on the network of pathological symptoms as a mutually reinforcing structure. On this model, high connectivity between the different network nodes or symptoms is the hallmark of a disordered mind. Denny concluded that according to this understanding of mental disorder, a disorder as an entity is more analogous to a flock of birds than to a unitary thing.

In his presentation ‘Fat or Obese – What Difference Does it Make?’ Andreas de Block considered objections to the medicalization of fatness by proponents of fat studies. He criticized the link fat studies scholars often make between pathologizing and moralizing and discussed studies which show some potential benefits of pathologizing obesity. Andreas also explored the possible effects of labelling obesity as a mental disorder analogous to addiction.


Carl Craver talked about mechanisms and psychiatric disorders. He defended the claim that identifying mechanisms is an essential part of understanding mental disorders. He stressed that mechanisms can be found at different levels, need not be purely biological and that a focus on mechanisms does not preclude looking at the interaction between individual and society. He then cautioned that we should however not expect mechanistic explanation to provide taxonomic distinctions between different disorders. 
  
Daniel Hartner and Kari Theurer’s talk addressed the 2013 Research Domain Criteria project’s attempt to improve diagnostics in psychiatry by focusing on functional domains rather than on clusters of symptoms. They warned that this framework neglects the normative aspect of the ascription of disorder by focusing on seemingly objective mechanisms and domains of functioning.

In her talk ‘Three Puzzles in the Logic of Psychiatric Classification’ Rachel Cooper considered 3 related questions: What are basic units that are classified in psychiatry, people or disorders? How should disorders be individuated? How can we distinguish between person and illness? She tentatively concluded that different answers might be more or less plausible for different kinds of mental disorders. Personality disorders or autism for example are disorders that don’t seem to lend themselves to an approach where the disorder can be abstracted away from the person, because they are such an integral part of who the person is and what they are like.

Elselijn Kingma gave a talk entitled ‘Three Reasons why Physical and Mental Disorder Differ’. One of the way in which our concepts of somatic and mental disorders vary are that we conceive of minor illnesses as single cause, self limiting conditions to which there is no equivalent in mental disorders. Furthermore, in the case of physical disorders we have a two step model which distinguishes between the disease itself and a failure in coping, whereas mental disorders are only diagnosed when there is a failure in coping.

Mael Lemoine explored the issue of how to biologize mental disorders, arguing that at present mental disorders as a category are imperfectly naturalized objects of science and that while social construction is relevant to scientific labelling, once a mental disorder has been naturalized the scientific definition will replace the social definition.

Markus Pawelzik attacked both the notion of a mental disorder and the idea that mental disorders can be naturalized. He stressed that while there is mental illness, the mental problems people suffer from are to diverse to be classified into disorder categories and that there are no disorder specific biological signatures which would allow the biologization of mental disorders.

This was an enjoyable and productive workshop which benefited from incorporating a large range of perspectives on the topic.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph