Skip to main content

Early Career Mind Network Event, Warwick


The Early Career Mind Network (ECMN) is a new initiative with the aim to establish a strong network of early career researchers in the philosophy of mind who do not yet have permanent positions in academic philosophy. On 27th to 28th April 2016 the University of Warwick hosted the first ECMN research forum, organised by Alisa Mandrigin. This blog post provides an overview of the research ideas explored by the researchers at the event.

Tom McClelland spoke first on the Grand Illusion Hypothesis (GIH). According to the GIH, we overestimate how rich visual experience is outside of focal attention. McClelland described empirical findings showing that our visual systems compensate for the limits of attention by encoding information about the average features of groups or crowds. McClelland outlined precisely how findings relating to this ‘ensemble perception’ should be viewed as important to the GIH. He denied that the findings show that there is no Grand Illusion, but argued that they do suggest that visual phenomenology is less diminished than the GIH might seem to suggest because our experience of things outside focal attention can be aided by ‘ensemble perception’.


 
Next Vivan Joseph asked how we should address the question of whether we can attend to an object while remaining unaware of it. He presented reasons for rejecting approaches to the question that involve a significant departure from the folk conception of attention. He argued, for example, that philosophers who discuss experimental data about blindsight (the ability to respond to visual stimuli without being conscious of it) when trying to answer whether we can attend to an object without being aware of it beg the question against those, such as William James, who argue that attention is the concentration of consciousness.



Max Jones discussed a debate between representationalists and enactivists. Representationalists explain perception by appealing to perceptual representations, with many arguing that we perceive by reconstructing representations of our local environment. Meanwhile, enactivists argue that perception does not use representations. Jones argued for a third option: that our perception of reality is facilitated by the representation of possibilities.



Joe Cunningham discussed the highest common factor (HCF) conception of rationalising explanation, according to which the explanation of one’s action in good cases, in which one acts in response to a fact in favour of one doing something, is in some significant sense the same as the explanation of one’s actions in bad cases, in which it only seems as if one is responding to a normatively significant fact. Cunningham argued that HCF can be interpreted in two ways. On the strong reading, the particular explanation in the good case is the same as that in the bad. On the weak reading, the same kind of explanation is appropriate in the good and bad case. He claimed that recent arguments developed by Hornsby (2008) and Roessler (2014) only succeed in undermining the strong version of the view. He then sketched a fresh argument effective against even the weak version of the view which appeals to certain claims about how good cases contrast with cases of weakness of will.



Barney Walker argued that philosophers writing about the value of knowledge have tacitly assumed that the way to answer the question of why we desire knowledge is to appeal to the claim that knowledge is better for a subject than mere true belief. He then focused on Williams’ claim that seekers of knowledge merely want to arrive at truth. He described a dilemma faced by Williams in defending this argument: (I) If the subject wants to know then it is not the case that all he wants is true belief, but (II) if the subject just wants to have a true belief then it is not clear why he should want to know. Walker proposed a solution to the dilemma: a subject has not arrived at a belief whether p unless the believer takes himself to have acquired knowledge that p. On this account, people want to know whether p because only when they have achieved this aim will they believe that p.



Tony Cheng argued that experiences that are about mind-independent objects imply an understanding of ourselves as physical objects in a world independent of language and self-knowledge. He claimed that all experiences that are about mind-independent objects require allocentric spatial representation, that is, representation that encodes information about the location of one object with respect to other objects. Then he argued that representation of this sort requires that we represent ourselves as situated in a mind-independent world.



Casey Doyle started with the premise that although it is possible to know of your intentional attitudes by testimony there seem to be reasons against doing so. He argued that an account of first-person authority ought to be able to explain this but the standard view, according to which we have epistemic privilege over our thoughts, cannot. He also claimed that there is no inherent weakness in testimony that explains why we should not depend upon it. Doyle proposed an agential model of first-person authority as an alternative explanation of first person authority. 



 
Lucy Campbell argued that practical knowledge (PK) – one’s knowledge of one’s own intentional action - relates to intention as ordinary empirical knowledge relates to belief. To support this claim she drew upon John Hyman's account of knowledge as the ability to use a fact as a reason. Campbell argued that the knowledge ability can be grounded in belief, but also in intention. Ordinary empirical knowledge has the first form; PK has the second.



The meeting finished with my talk. I discussed how humans seem to face an ethical/epistemic dilemma; ethics demands that we treat people equally, as equally likely to possess certain traits, but if knowledge is our aim we should reflect how different social groups tend to possess some features at different rates. I used psychological research to argue that the best choice from the epistemic perspective is frequently the best choice from the ethical perspective: avoiding stereotyping even when this involves failing to reflect social realities.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...