Skip to main content

A Political Justification of Nudges


This post is by Francesco Guala (pictured above), Professor of Economics at the University of Milan. In this post, he presents a paper he wrote with Luigi Mittone, Professor of Economics at the University of Trento, and which was published in the journal Review of Philosophy and Psychology. A reply to their article by Cass Sunstein is also available in the same journal.

‘Behavioural economics’ is a research programme that aims at making economic models psychologically more realistic. After many years ‘in the wild’, behavioural economists are now part of the mainstream and have succeeded at bringing microeconomics in line with the developments of cognitive psychology.

Up until recently, however, behavioural economists had been rather shy regarding the normative (i.e. policy) implications of their research. All of this has changed in 2008 with the publication of Nudge, the best-selling book by Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler. Nudge is not only an impressive showcase for the best social policies inspired by behavioural economists. It also offers a philosophical framework to justify the use of behavioural interventions. The framework is called ‘Libertarian Paternalism’: nudges are libertarian because they influence people’s behaviour without limiting the range of options available to them; they are paternalistic because they help people choose the options that are good for them.

Libertarian Paternalism, predictably, has attracted a lot of criticism. Some have pointed out that nudges are not really libertarian, others that they are not really paternalistic. In this recent paper, Luigi Mittone and I argue that they should not be paternalistic. We explain that paternalism is largely a red herring, because some of the most advertised nudges involve interventions that are not easily justifiable as welfare-improving for the individual citizen who is nudged, but that are better justified as being for the good of the society as a whole.

Our chief examples are the behavioural policies aimed at tackling problems of intertemporal discounting. Consider Ann, a young woman who can either decide to save a substantial part of her income to build a pension, or spend the money now, traveling around the world and having fun with her friends. A scheme that nudges Ann to save for the future – for example, by making investment in a pension fund the default option when she signs her contract – is justifiable as satisfying ‘old Ann’s’ preference for a comfortable retirement. But it clearly goes against ‘young Ann’s’ preference for living an interesting and exciting life right now.

Problems of multiple selves, of course, are not new to philosophers or economists. One possible reaction is to say that Sunstein and Thaler should openly take sides – they should come up with a reason to sacrifice ‘young Ann’s’ welfare in favour of ‘old Ann’s’ welfare. This move however does not seem to come cheaply and would require quite a lot of argumentation. Thus Luigi Mittone and I propose a different solution: we should recognize that nudge policies are better defended from a political rather than a moral perspective. The reason we want Ann to save money is not necessarily or principally that we care for her older self. It is rather that a society full of old people who have not saved enough for their pensions is unsustainable and likely to give rise to tremendous tensions.

Those of us who live in Southern Europe, unfortunately, are well aware of this problem: a large group of elderly people can easily lobby the government and influence policies that, effectively, force younger generations to support their myopic elders – through higher taxes, low unemployment subsidies, or simply by making their retirement practically impossible.

Of course most of us appreciate (most) nudge policies, especially those that may help avoid situations of this kind. But the reason we like them is that we want to live in a peaceful society and we care for the welfare of all the citizens – the singing crickets as much as the hard-working ants. That’s why we should better take a contractarian perspective and justify nudges politically, rather than endorse Sunstein and Thaler’s dubious ‘paternalistic’ philosophy.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph