Skip to main content

Belief and Belief Formation Workshop

The Centre for Philosophical Psychology at the University of Antwerp held a workshop on the 27th November 2018 on the topic of belief and belief formation. Here’s a brief summary of the excellent talks given at the workshop, kindly written by Dan Williams.




Neil Levy (Oxford/Macquarie) gave the first talk, entitled ‘Not so hypocritical after all: how we change our minds without noticing’. Levy focused on a phenomenon that many people assume to be a form of hypocrisy—namely, cases in which individuals come to change their beliefs about, say, politics when popular opinion (or the popular opinion within their relevant tribe or coalition) changes. (Levy gave the example of many ‘Never Trumpers’ who then apparently changed their opinion of Trump when he came to power).

Levy argued that at least some examples of this phenomenon are in fact not best understood as a form of hypocrisy; rather, they arise from people forming beliefs “rationally”. Specifically, he drew attention to two important features of human belief formation: first, our evolutionary dependence on cumulative cultural evolution, and the suite of psychological mechanisms that facilitate the cultural learning that underlies it; second, the way in which we offload representational states such as beliefs onto the surrounding environment. 

These two features of human psychology, Levy argued, can help to explain many apparent examples of hypocrisy: when an individual radically changes his or her opinion on, say, Trump, this need not be an example of motivated reasoning, “tribalism”, or hypocrisy; rather, it can simply be a result of these—usually adaptive and truth-tracking—features of human psychology.

Eric Mandelbaum (CUNY) gave the second talk on ‘The Fragmentation of Belief’. Mandelbaum sought to develop a form of “psychofunctionalism”, according to which beliefs are best understood as real entities within the mind that play the functional role of beliefs as described by our best contemporary cognitive science. 

Psychofunctionalism has traditionally been held back, Mandelbaum argued, by the lack of concrete proposals on what the relevant psychological laws or regularities that actually govern belief formation consist in. To address this, Mandelbaum sought to sketch a cognitive architecture, focusing specifically on the issue of how beliefs are stored. 

At the core of his proposal was the idea that belief storage is highly fragmented; rather than a unified web of belief, he argued that our best research in cognitive science supports a view of our cognitive architecture as consisting of many distinct, independently accessible data structures which Mandelbaum calls ‘fragments’. 

This architecture, Mandelbaum argued, generates many psychological phenomena that standard “web of belief”-based theories struggle to account for, such as inconsistent beliefs, redundant beliefs, and distinct bodies of information on the same subject.

The third speaker was Marianna Bergamaschi Ganapini (Union College), speaking on the topic of ‘Belief’s Minimal Rationality’. Ganapini focused on apparent examples of beliefs such as clinical delusions and conspiracy theories that lack many of the prototypical characteristics of beliefs. 

She argued against both traditionalist view of belief, which describe very high standards for something to achieve the status of a belief, and a revisionist position, which grants the status of belief to mental states on very minimal grounds (for example, whether someone is willing to sincerely assert that they hold the belief). 

She then put forward a view of beliefs called “Moderate Traditionalism”, which constitutes a kind of middle-path between these two options. The upshot of this view, she argued, is that some delusions and conspiracy theorists will not qualify as beliefs even if the individuals that harbour them sincerely assert that they believe them.

Jake Quilty-Dunn (Oxford) gave the fourth talk on ‘Functionalism about Belief’. Quilty-Dunn criticised widespread functionalist views of beliefs and other propositional attitudes, according to which beliefs are mental states that perform specific functional roles. He first sought to explore what these putative functional roles might be, focusing especially on the psychological laws/regularities that beliefs apparently participate in according to cognitive dissonance theory. 

After clarifying the commitments of cognitive dissonance theory and developing its emphasis on the importance of maintaining a positive self-concept, he argued that we should nevertheless resist standard psychofunctionalist views that draw on theories such as cognitive dissonance theory to identify the core functional role of beliefs. 

Instead, he proposed a “primitivist” alternative to psychofunctionalism, according to which propositional attitudes should be understood as primitive formal properties of certain mental states, analogous to the way in which symbols are individuated by their formal properties.

The final talk was given by Neil Van Leeuwen (Georgia State) on ‘Two Theoretical Roles for “Belief”’. Van Leeuwen argued that vast numbers of philosophers and cognitive scientists have mistakenly assumed that two very different theoretical roles associated with the term “belief” identify the same kind of psychological state. 

The first theoretical role of “mundane beliefs” identifies the functional properties associated with commonsense beliefs: what’s in the fridge, what time is the football game on, what’s the capital of France, and so on. The second theoretical role of “groupish beliefs” identifies the functional properties associated with beliefs whose function is to signal the believer’s group identity (e.g. religious beliefs). 

Van Leeuwen argued that the functional roles associated with these two mental states are so different that we should resist the widespread view that they both amount to the same kind of mental state.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph