Skip to main content

Superstitious Confabulations

In this post, Anna IchinoPostdoctoral Research Fellow at the University of Milan, working primarily in the philosophy of mind and philosophical psychology, continues our series of research posts on the special issue in Topoi, introducing her paper "Superstitious confabulations". 


Confabulation is a heterogenous phenomenon, which varies across a number of dimensions – including content, mode of elicitation, aetiology, and more. While acknowledging this heterogeneity, recent philosophical discussions have focussed mostly on some particular kinds of confabulation: notably, confabulations that are about the self, and externally elicited – classic examples being cases of memory distortions and of ‘choice blindness’. With a few exceptions, such discussions highlight the epistemic faults of these confabulations, especially in relation to self-knowledge.

In my paper, I draw the attention to a different sort of confabulations, which are typically about the world (as opposed to the self), and spontaneous (as opposed to externally elicited). I call them ‘superstitious confabulations’, since they originate in the domain of superstitious thinking and practices. I argue that these sorts of confabulations are peculiar in that they are often entertained in a non-doxastic way – with positive consequences for the assessment of their epistemic rationality; and that they can teach us important lessons on the epistemic and normative status of confabulations more in general.

I start by introducing superstitious thinking, broadly construed so as to include not only traditional superstitions like those concerning broken mirrors or black cats, but also a variety of more idiosyncratic superstitious ideas concerning such things as lucky charms, propitiatory rituals, telepathic connections, hidden conspiracies, etc. – that are shown to be pervasive both in clinical and non-clinical populations (see e.g. Risen 2016; Vyse 2014).

I argue that this sort of thinking, characterised by a tendency to exaggerate the world’s meaningfulness and coherence, shares many key features with paradigmatic confabulations – including ill-groundedness, motivational origins, gap-filling function, and lack of deceitful intentions.

Although of course there are also some differences between superstitions and paradigmatic confabulations, we can think of them as variations within the same broad psychological family – thereby recognizing, in our heterogenous confabulation category, the existence of a sub-class of ‘superstitious confabulations’.

Why does it matter to recognize that? It matters for our general understanding of how the mind works – making us realise how pervasive certain features of our cognition are. And it matters for a better understanding of the two phenomena of confabulation and superstition in particular – fostering closer interactions between research programs in these two areas, which so far have gone on in almost total disregard from each other.

In the second part of the paper I provide an example of how fruitful such interactions can be. I argue that an important psychological model recently developed to explain superstitious attitudes reveals such attitudes to be non-doxastic in nature, and that this model may be applied also to other more standard forms of confabulation – in both cases with important implications for the sorts of normative questions that philosophers have been asking about these phenomena.

The model in question is the ‘dual-system model of magical thinking’ defended by Jane Risen (2016, 2017) – according to which superstitious attitudes are formed via the motivationally biased heuristics of System 1, and subsequently maintained through what Risen calls System 2’s ‘acquiescence’: a process by which ideas that are explicitly understood to be false or ungrounded are nonetheless willingly endorsed and allowed to play action-guiding roles.

I argue that ‘acquiescence’, so characterised, is clearly a non-doxastic process: as Williams (1973) famously pointed out, beliefs are not the sorts of attitudes that can be willingly endorsed in the face of explicitly acknowledged counter-evidence. Hence, Risen’s account speaks in favour of superstitious attitudes’ non-doxastic nature. And insofar as it is right, superstitions may turn out to be less epistemically irrational than they are typically taken to be (although – note – this does not make them immune from other sorts of criticisms!).

I conclude by outlining some reasons why a similar non-doxastic account may also apply to (at least some) more paradigmatic forms of confabulation – in particular to those ‘primary confabulations’ that are stubbornly maintained in the face of counterevidence and counterarguments. Once again, this non-doxastic approach would put pressure on common assumptions about confabulations’ epistemic irrationality – an upshot that looks especially relevant for the burgeoning research program concerning confabulation’s ‘epistemic innocence’ (see e.g. Bortolotti and Sullivan-Bissett 2018).

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph