Skip to main content

Explaining Delusions Symposium at ICP 2016

Pacifico, Yokohama
PERFECT was invited to present a symposium at the 31st International Congress of Psychology (ICP), which took place at Pacifico Yokohama in Japan and was attended by over 8000 people from 95 countries. The symposium, entitled ‘Explaining Delusion: Empirical and Theoretical Approaches to Delusion Formation’ featured speakers from philosophy (myself, Rachel Gunn), Kengo Miyazono and Phillip Gerrans) and from psychology (Eriko Sugimori and Rochelle Cox).

Eriko Sugimori’s talk entitled ‘Effects of Positive and Negative Delusional Ideation on Memory’ covered a study where participants were given a learning task in which they were shown 40 adjectives projected one at a time on a screen.  Fifteen minutes later they were shown 80 adjectives and asked to state whether those adjectives had featured in the learning task. The participants were assessed for delusion proneness as well as degree of positive delusional ideation (consisting of traits such as guardedness, self-conceit, sense of specialness, and manipulativeness towards others) and negative delusional ideation (consisting of traits such as alienation, belittlement, persecution, and harming of others).  Participants with high delusional ideation were more likely to indicate that they had learned adjectives that they had not actually learned.

In a second experiment, two forced-choice tests were conducted immediately after the learning phase.  Pairs of words with similar meanings one with a positive and one with a negative connotation (eg: careful-skeptical, adventurous-reckless etc.) were presented. At the initial test phase, when presented with a forced-choice, participants were all relatively accurate in their recall (regardless of score for delusion-proneness). As time passed (when tested daily over several days) the proportion of false alarms increased among those with high proneness to delusional ideation and was correlated with their delusional style (ie those with positive traits had more false alarms with regard to positive adjectives and those with negative traits had more false alarms with regard to negative adjectives). 


Kengo Miyazono’s ‘Hybrid Theory of Delusion Formation’ argues that the two-factor theory of delusion formation can be integrated with the account of delusion formation in which the notion of prediction-error plays the central role.  In prediction-error theory delusions are formed in response to aberrant prediction-error signals (signals that indicate a mismatch between expectation and actual experience).  In the two-factor account delusions are formed as a result of two distinct factors, these are:  1) the formation of a delusional idea and 2) the maintenance of (or inability to reject) that idea.  Miyazono argues that a mis-match between expectations and actual experience could account for how a delusional idea arises due to its affect on attention allocation.  Alternatively, prediction-error problems might account for the maintenance of a delusion by making belief updating excessively revisionist.  In either case, on his account, prediction-error theory and two-factor accounts of delusion need not be incompatible.

Rochelle Cox’s talk gave us some results from her experiments on modelling delusions of misidentification using hypnosis and examining techniques that encourage belief revision.  In her research she uses hypnosis to cause people to have temporary, reversible pathological ‘symptoms’ (such as delusions of misidentification) to provide an opportunity to examine belief maintenance and revision in the laboratory.  Her research involves mistaken beliefs about the identity of oneself, other people, places, or objects and aims to identify techniques to encourage subjects to abandon their suggested beliefs.  Results indicate that the most successful techniques involve active reality testing or providing subjects with an alternative explanation for their anomalous experiences. The advantages and disadvantages of these hypnotic models were discussed alongside the clinical implications of the findings.

Philip Gerrans gave a talk entitled ‘The Default Mode Network and the Cognitive Architecture of Belief Fixation. A New Approach to the One Stage -Two Stage Debate about Delusion Formation.’  Gerrans argues that delusions occur as a result of the specialized circuitry that constructs the raw material for subjective narrative interpretations of experience: The Default Mode Network (DMN) responding to anomalous or highly salient experiences. He argues that this interpretation makes sense of the phenomenology of delusions and of the neural evidence about the way the DMN and right dorsolateral-prefrontal cortex interact in psychiatric conditions.  He further argues that this approach replaces debates about the rationality or irrationality of delusional beliefs with a new debate around the nature of the cognitive aetiology of delusion.

In my talk entitled ‘Delusion: A Philosophical Conceptualisation from Original Empirical Work’ I argue that some delusions should not be thought of in terms of the standard clinical definition where the focus is on false beliefs held with conviction.  Whilst we might come to understand that someone is ill based on her reporting apparent beliefs held with conviction in the face of counter evidence, in some cases the pathology lies in her direct perceptual experience.  Interviews with people who have clinically significant delusions highlights the bizarre and persistent nature of these anomalous perceptual experiences.  I argue (along with other one-factor theorists) that in these cases no cognitive or reasoning deficit is required for these kinds of delusions to arise.  We ordinarily prioritise direct experience over other information, people with these kinds of experience find them impossible to ignore and, as they persist and intensify, the experience demands an explanation.



At the end of the symposium a short but lively discussion panel, chaired by Kathy Puddifoot, was held highlighting the diversity of views and how little can really be agreed upon with regard to the complex and heterogeneous nature of delusion.  All the abstracts from the ICP 2016 can be found here at Wiley Online.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph