Skip to main content

Rescuing the ‘Loss-of-Agency’ Account of Thought Insertion

Today's post is by Patrizia Pedrini (University of Florence). Here she summarises her recent paper, “Rescuing the ‘Loss-of-Agency’ Account of Thought Insertion”, which appeared in Philosophy, Psychiatry, & Psychology in 2015.


Every day we think hundreds of thoughts. We form opinions, hold beliefs, develop intentions, feel desires, emotions, sensations, entertain fantasies. All this thinking activity typically comes to our consciousness with a fundamental feature that seems as natural as the thinking it accompanies: our capacity for self-ascription of it. When we think a thought, we also self-ascribe that thought, and such capacity for self-ascription is routine, immediate, unproblematic.

However, this is a capacity that can break down. There is a disorder, known as thought insertion, that occurs in people diagnosed with schizophrenia and related forms of mental illness, the puzzling feature of which appears to amount to the impairment of such capacity. The subject affected by thought insertion experiences his thinking activity as made for or done to herself by someone else – a person or intelligent form other than himself (cf. Graham 2004, p. 89).

In the attempt to specify how the capacity for self-ascription of a thought can break down, thought insertion has also often been explained as a failure of the “sense of agency”, not of ownership, which latter the patient is thought to retain. The “loss-of-agency” view of thought insertion has been held by a number of cognitive scientists, psychiatrists, and also philosophers (e.g., Stephens and Graham 1994a, 1994b, 2000; O'Brien and Opie 2003; Gallagher 2004; Peacocke 2008). Their main hypothesis is that a thought is pathologically “inserted” when it is not voluntarily caused by the subject, that is, when the subject has not formed it qua agent.

The presupposition that underlies this view is that in the ordinary, non-pathological case of thoughts that we do not experience as inserted, we all have a “sense of agency” for those non-inserted thoughts whose breakdown would be the very cause of the pathological condition of thought insertion. That is, thoughts become experienced as “inserted” when the subject has not actively and voluntarily formed them herself, as she would experience instead in normal circumstances. According to Bortolotti (2010), this account is unsatisfactory: most of our ordinary thoughts are not typically accompanied by the sense that they have been voluntarily produced by us, and yet they are not regarded as “inserted”, so the cause of thought insertion cannot be the loss of agency invoked by the defenders of the “loss-of-agency” account of thought insertion, and must lie elsewhere.

Bortolotti presents an account of thought insertion according to which the pathological experience of feeling that one’s thoughts are “inserted” is not caused by a “loss of agency” on the part of the subject involved. Bortolotti elaborates an alternative view according to which thought insertion is mainly due to a failure to “endorse” the thought on the part of the subject: it is not that the subject suffering from thought insertion has not voluntarily caused or produced the thought, so that she then experiences it as inserted; rather, she is not able to endorse it, independently of how the thought has been caused or produced.




Whilst I agree with Bortolotti that the Endorsement Model is preferable to the Traditional “Loss-of-Agency” Account of thought insertion in that the former rightly assumes that the volitional aspects of agency do not apply to most ordinary, non-pathological thoughts, this does not show that agency is not extensively involved in non-pathological thinking. On the contrary, agency is systematically connected with non-pathological thinking, although not ordinarily in the form of the volitional agentive capacity to produce thoughts intentionally, exactly as Bortolotti diagnoses.

I thus rely on a transcendental argument borrowed from Bilgrami (2006) which diagnoses a local failure of the agency ordinarily underlying non-pathological thinking as its condition of possibility: only someone who is an agent can have thoughts disposing her to understand what it is to act upon them in what I will call the “cause/reason-giving practice”, and those dispositions make for the experience that the ordinary subject has of being agentively involved in such thinking.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...