Skip to main content

What Makes Delusions Pathological?


My name is Valentina Petrolini and I am a doctoral candidate at the University of Cincinnati. I work in philosophy of psychiatry, where my research focuses on the nature of mental disorders and on pathologies of belief such as delusions.

In my paper “What Makes Delusions Pathological?” I draw on Lisa Bortolotti’s work to suggest that delusional beliefs are irrational in a particular way. I accept the Continuity Thesis that Bortolotti proposes, namely the idea that beliefs lie on a continuum of rationality with delusions at the most irrational end. Yet, this formulation leaves an important problem unsolved. If delusions cannot be distinguished from other irrational beliefs by their failure to live up to rational norms, what makes delusions distinctively pathological? My solution consists in fine-tuning the notion of rationality to explore the influence that processes like emotions and relevance detection have on belief formation.

Why are norms insufficient? On Bortolotti’s view, delusions and ordinary irrational beliefs fail to meet the standards of canonical rational norms. For example, both persecutory delusions and superstitious beliefs tend to be incoherent (procedural irrationality), resistant to contrary evidence (epistemic irrationality), and at odds with behavior (agential irrationality). However, we still want to distinguish between someone who believes that aliens are persecuting him and someone who believes that wearing her mother’s necklace will help during the exam. The Continuity Thesis alone cannot help us to do that, because ordinary beliefs may be irrational according to all the norms while failing to qualify as delusional.

Why are relevance detection and emotions important? Labeling a person as “rational”, we want to stress her ability to form beliefs or undertake actions that are in accordance with her goals in a way that is responsive to the current context. If the library catches fire, it would not be rational for me to stop by a shelf to pick up a book. Relevance detection is thus the ability that allows us to focus attention on certain stimuli and to determine which aspects of the environment are important. How do we do that? Cognitively speaking, executive functions allow us to switch between different tasks, incorporate relevant information, and filter out inappropriate responses. Recent work by Luiz Pessoa and colleagues has convincingly connected these abilities with emotional processing. Indeed, Pessoa’s experiments show that stimuli with high emotional significance (e.g. threatening facial expressions) take more time to be processed and often interfere with performance.

From emotions to delusions. I argue that delusional subjects exhibit an executive disturbance that is rooted in an emotional one. Emotions help us direct our attention: in the library example, fear prompts me to look for the nearest exit and to disregard the book. In these ordinary cases there seems to be a certain “fit” between the items highlighted by emotions and the subject’s goals. By contrast, in delusional cases the attribution of significance is importantly misplaced. Seeing that a lamp-post is unlit, hearing a dog barking, or noticing that one’s partner ties his shoes differently are causes of deep emotional turmoil. As a result, the patient’s attention becomes directed toward the items that need to be processed to provide an explanation of their significance. The endorsement of a particular delusion (e.g. “I live in a reality show”) may then result from the attempt to explain why other people’s gazes appear invasive or threatening. Executive deficits, such as resistance to counterevidence, originate from an emotional disturbance that forces patients to invest resources in processing highly affective but irrelevant stimuli. Delusions can thus be characterized as executive and emotional dysfunctions.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph