Skip to main content

Neuropsychiatry Conference 2018

The Royal College of Psychiatrists hosted its Faculty of Neuropsychiatry Annual Conference on 13-14 September 2018 in London. I was fortunate to attend the first day and I am going to report on some of the interesting talks I listened to.



In the first session speakers focused on neuroscience for psychiatrists, and Paul Johns, author of Clinical Neuroscience, addressed the functional anatomy of the human amygdala.

The amygdala is constantly looking out for dangers and helps us evaluate the emotional significance of events. It facilitates social interactions as it enables us to read other people's minds. Further, the amygdala is involved in learning and episodic memory for important events. It is responsible for an implicit emotional memory of negative events to help us avoid adverse stimuli.

The amygdala is for assessing environmental cues to determine the adequate response to threats. So patients without the amygdala are fearless but it is possible to experimentally induce a panic attack by giving them the impression that they are suffocating. So the amygdala is not necessary for feeling scared (the hypothalamus is).

The second speaker, Nandini Mullatti (King's College London), described the role of neurophysiology in mental health settings with a focus on epilepsy. By looking at some patients' history and at the manifestation of unusual symptoms (e.g., a woman claiming "she was losing her face"), Mullatti showed that clinical neurophysiology provides evidence to decide whether symptoms are organic or functional and further has an important role to play in the evaluation of functional symptoms.

The third speaker in this session, Oliver Robinson (University College London), addressed the history of neuroimaging in mood and anxiety. He focused on depression (unipolar and bipolar) and showed some inconsistent imaging results about whether these conditions are correlated with increased or decreased activity in the subgenual cingulate region of the brain.



Robinson moved to the prediction error model and the learning process. In depression, people seem to have reduced responses to positive events but increases responses to adverse events. That means that they learn differently and do not adapt their behaviour to the stimuli available to them in the same way as people without depression. This points to an affective bias. However, recent studies conflict with this simple picture which leads to a cautious approach to the applications of neuroimaging.

In the second session, on Conceptions of the Mind, Andrea Cavanna (Aston University) presented on behavioural neurology. He started from a clear and engaging summary of the evolution of the human brain to characterise some disorders as the reptilian brain taking over and no longer being kept in check by the innovations to be found in the mammalian or neo-mammalian brain. Cavanna used the case of Tourette syndrome to illustrate some of the key points.

I was the second speaker (Lisa Bortolotti, University of Birmingham) and talked about how the delusions literature can inform our conception of beliefs, rationality, and mental health. In short, I argued that some commonly held beliefs about the consequences of irrationality are revealed to be myths once we take delusions to be paradigmatic instances of epistemic irrationality.

I made a case for the following: (1) epistemically irrational beliefs are not un-understandable and can help us interpret affective responses and behaviour; (2) epistemically irrational beliefs are not all bad, and can have beneficial consequences for wellbeing, knowledge, and success; (3) epistemically irrational beliefs are not an exception in a largely rational belief system.

Karl Friston (University of College London) was the third speaker in the Conceptions of the Mind session. He started explaining the signs and symptoms of schizophrenia in terms of false inference and introduced the history of the Bayesian brain theory. Perception is hypothesis casting and most of what we do is go through life minimising prediction error. This approach gives us a good story of the positive symptoms of schizophrenia: sensory constraints are disconnected from the higher end of the process where we adopt beliefs that are models of the world.

Day 1 of the conference was very intense and informative for an interdisciplinary audience and provided some suggestions for how to improve clinical practice.


Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph