Skip to main content

Factor One, Familiarity and Frontal Cortex

In this post, Phil Corlett, Associate Professor of Psychiatry at Yale School of Medicine, discusses some of the ideas in his paper ‘Factor one, familiarity and frontal cortex: a challenge to the two-factor theory of delusions’ recently published in the Journal of Cognitive Neuropsychiatry.


Over recent years, Imperfect Cognitions has become the premier hub and outlet for work on the neurobiology and cognitive psychology of delusions. It has featured my work on aberrant prediction error and delusions in schizophrenia (Corlett et al., 2007), and work that conceptually replicates it (Kaplan et al., 2016). There has been work, also highlighted on the blog, from neurological patients that suggest instead that a 2-factor explanation of delusions may be more appropriate (Darby et al., 2017), although that work was not conclusive (McKay and Furl, 2017).

It has all garnered much interest. Partly because delusions inherently fascinating, I think, and partly because the arguments being waged have clinical import as well as more broad appeal – they are about our beliefs, which we all cherish and often find hard to relinquish. These debates also factor on how best to map the mind and brain. Whilst the debate is about delusions, it has more wide-ranging implications.

Recently I uncovered something in the literature which I believe undermines the 2-factor theory of delusions (Davies et al., 2001, Coltheart, 2010, Coltheart et al., 2011). I believe this discovery warrants our consideration, and, my own reflection has led me to raise four objections to the factor theory of delusions. Two of those are about the control cases who are a foundational for the 2-factor theory of Capgras delusion (the flagship of the 2-factor explanatory fleet). 

One further objection is about the evidence base when it comes to other monothematic delusions. And a final objection is with regards to how we ought to map-mind to brain, whether encapsulated modularity obtains when it comes to belief and perception. If beliefs do alter perception, that is a problem for 2-factor theory.

Briefly, 2-factor theory was devised to explain the monothematic delusions that arise following traumatic brain injury, such as Capgras (that a loved one, familiar conspecific or object has been replaced by an imposter that looks the same but does not feel the same). The 2-Factor explanation holds that people experience the lack of familiarity for their loved one (Factor 1) and they adopt the belief that they are an imposter because they have a belief evaluation deficit (Factor 2) (Davies et al., 2001, Coltheart, 2010, Coltheart et al., 2011)

It is argued that a second factor is necessary because there exist neuropsychological patients who lack familiarity responses to familiar faces, but do not have delusions (Tranel et al., 1995) – these people are the focus of my update. Their familiarity response is usually operationalized as changes in their skin conductance to famous faces like Marilyn Monroe or Margaret Thatcher. Since they lack these changes, but do not have delusions, 2-factor theorists suggest a second, delusion-generating factor is needed.

2-factor theory is based on the observation that these cases all have circumscribed damage in bilateral ventromedial prefrontal cortex (Tranel et al., 1995). People with neurological delusions usually have additional damage to dorsolateral prefrontal cortex, often on the right (Davies et al., 2001, Coltheart, 2010, Coltheart et al., 2011).

2-factor theory for Capgras then suggests that vmPFC damage subtends Factor 1 (the loss of familiarity response to familiar faces, so ‘That doesn’t feel like my wife’) and rDLPFC damage underlies Factor 2 (inappropriately adopting the belief that my wife is an imposter) (Davies et al., 2001, Coltheart, 2010, Coltheart et al., 2011).

In reviewing the literature, I recently discovered a paper by Damasio and Tranel (Tranel and Damasio, 1994) that reports more about those 4 cases. I learned that the 4 cases who lack familiarity responses to familiar faces and have vmPFC damage have:

  1. More extensive damage – including to dorsolateral prefrontal cortex and right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex in particular (Tranel and Damasio, 1994)
  2. Have more extensive skin conductance changes beyond familiar faces – they lack a response to almost all psychologically salient visual stimuli (Tranel and Damasio, 1994).
Thus, my first two objections to 2-factor theory:
  1. rDLPFC damage is not sufficient for belief evaluation dysfunction as claimed by 2-factor theorists
  2. The cases on which Factor 1 is predicated do not have a specific enough deficit to determine the Capgras delusion content. Since the 4 cases lack arousal responses to all kinds of salient stimuli.
Taken together, these two points call for a re-appraisal and of 2-factor theory. At the very least, they ought not to be called VMPFC controls. If they do not share the same SCR deficit as Capgras patients, then they ought not serve as the logical basis for demanding a second deficit in belief evaluation.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...