Skip to main content

Measles, Magic and Misidentifications

I'm Ryan McKay, Professor of Psychology at Royal Holloway, University of London, and head of the Royal Holloway Morality and Beliefs Lab (MaB-Lab). I'm interested in how we form and revise beliefs, including delusional beliefs. This post is a summary of my article “Measles, Magic and Misidentifications: A Defence of the Two-Factor Theory of Delusions” in reply to Phil Cortlett's recent paper discussed on the blog last week.



The Two-Factor Theory of Delusions

One may (a) interpret data falsely, but also (b) receive false data for interpretation.
~ Southard, 1912, p. 328.

The idea that delusions arise when individuals attempt to interpret “false data” has been incorporated in several theories of delusions. Two-factor theorists, however (e.g., Coltheart et al., 2011; Davies & Coltheart, 2000; Langdon & Coltheart, 2000), view deluded individuals both as “receiving false data for interpretation” (factor one, which furnishes the content of the delusion) and as “interpreting data falsely” (factor two). Factor two is necessary, they claim, because some patients who appear to “receive false data for interpretation” are not delusional. The two-factor theory is thus based on the dissociation between “false data” and “false belief”.

Take Capgras delusion, for instance. For two-factor theorists, the “false data” in the Capgras case is a deficient autonomic response to familiar faces (indexed by skin conductance response [SCR]). The apparent dissociation between these “false data” and “false belief” comes from the fact that patients with damage to ventromedial prefrontal cortex (vmPFC) have also been shown to have deficient SCRs to familiar faces ¬– but these patients are not delusional (Tranel et al., 1995). So, something must explain why Capgras patients – but not the vmPFC patients – adopt the delusion. For two-factor theorists, that “something” is a deficient ability to evaluate candidate explanations of false data – the eponymous factor two.


Corlett’s Critique
Phil Corlett (in press) presents a bruising critique of the two-factor theory of delusions. In his view the theory is “an erroneous summary of rather scant evidence”; its “acolytes” not so much scientists as custodians of a kind of holy relic. The heart of Phil’s critique is two challenges he derives from a paper by Tranel and Damasio (1994), which illuminates the autonomic responses and brain damage of the vmPFC patients often cited in support of the two-factor theory of Capgras delusion. Here I summarise each challenge, and my response, in turn.

Corlett’s Challenge to Factor OnePhil notes that the vmPFC patients lacked normal SCRs not just to familiar faces but to psychologically salient visual stimuli more generally. From this, he concludes that the patients viewed by two-factor theorists as having the first factor in Capgras delusion, but not the second, “do not have a specific enough deficit to determine the Capgras delusion content”.

My Response
Phil claims that two-factor theorists have not acknowledged the specificity (or lack thereof) of the vmPFC patients’ SCR deficits. But that isn’t true. In fact, Langdon and Coltheart (2000) – in perhaps the seminal paper on the two-factor theory – considered this challenge at some length (see p. 191 of their paper). Indeed, because of these doubts about whether these vmPFC patients represent appropriate first-factor analogues of Capgras patients, Langdon and Coltheart (2000) went on to discuss other cases that they viewed as potentially more compelling in this regard. This undercuts an implicit premise of Phil’s overall argument – that whether the two-factor theory of delusions stands or falls depends on its success in explaining Capgras delusion specifically.

Corlett’s Challenge to Factor Two
Phil notes that two of the four vmPFC patients documented in Tranel and Damasio (1994) had damage to right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (rDLPFC), from which he concludes that “rDLPFC damage is not sufficient for belief evaluation dysfunction as claimed by two-factor theorists”. Phil says it is “troubling” that two-factor theorists have not acknowledged the DLPFC lesions of these four vmPFC cases, “despite [the theory] having been proposed almost 20 years ago”.

My Response
Phil implies that evidence of rDLPFC damage in these patients overturns two decades of theorizing by two-factor proponents. However, most claims about the anatomical localization of factor two have been more general, implicating dysfunction in the right hemisphere (e.g., Davies & Coltheart, 2000), right frontal cortex (e.g., Coltheart, 2007; Coltheart et al., 2007) or – based, in part, on Phil’s own work (Corlett et al., 2007) – right lateral prefrontal cortex (e.g., Coltheart, 2010; Coltheart et al., 2011). More specific claims about damage to right dorsolateral prefrontal cortex (rDLPFC) as the neuroanatomical substrate of factor two are relatively recent, and relatively tentative, e.g:

“[T]he evidence seems clear that damage to right frontal cortex is associated with the presence of delusional belief, and even that the specific region of right frontal cortex that is critical here is rLPFC ¬– and possibly an even more specific region, rDLPFC” (Coltheart et al., 2018, p. 237, my emphasis).

In any case, rDLPFC is still a huge and heterogeneous region of the brain, so even substantial damage to rDLPFC might not disrupt the circuits critical for belief evaluation, assuming rDLPFC is indeed the locus of those circuits.

Conclusion
Phil’s first challenge has been previously addressed, and his second challenge is, at best, overstated. In my view, these challenges do not negate the two-factor account. Moreover, recent work by Darby and colleagues (2017) provides compelling independent evidence that two independent factors – disruption to a familiarity network and to a belief evaluation network – underpin misidentification delusions such as Capgras delusion. But this is not to imply that two-factor theory can rest on its laurels. Two-factor theorists – and computational psychiatrists – should continue to devise and test falsifiable predictions of their respective theories.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo...

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph...