Skip to main content

Critical Phenomenology and Hermeneutical Injustice in Mental Health

Today's post is by Rosa Ritunnano (University of Birmingham and Melbourne), consultant psychiatrist and PhD candidate at the Institute for Mental Health, Birmingham, UK. Here she talks her recent paper which has been awarded the 2021 Wolfe Mays Essay Prize for Early Career Researchers by The British Society for Phenomenology (BSP) and the Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology (JBSP). 

Rosa Ritunnano

In this paper, I argue that the adoption of a critical phenomenological stance may improve conditions of hermeneutical marginalisation as experienced by individuals who have attracted a diagnosis of psychosis (although I believe that the suggested approach can be transferrable to other conditions).

In cases of hermeneutical injustice, one is unable to understand their own experience or effectively communicate it to others because they lack an adequate conceptual framework for making sense of this experience. The classic example used in the literature on hermeneutical injustice is women’s inability to adequately understand or describe experiences of sexual harassment before the concept ‘sexual harassment’ was coined and entered popular usage.

In mental healthcare, hermeneutical marginalisation may occur for different reasons. On the one hand, the person may start from a position of disadvantage when it comes to having adequate interpretive tools at their disposal. This is because they may already belong to a (environmentally, economically, socially) disadvantaged group whose access to hermeneutic resources is limited, or because their interpretations are (systemically or individually) dismissed. In the latter situation, individuals may have developed their own hermeneutical tools or equipment to make sense of a certain experience but, despite such understanding, their perspective is not given uptake by the listener(s). This is what philosopher Kristie Dotson has called ‘contributory injustice’. To illustrate, contributory injustice in psychiatry can be found in reports of service users who hear voices, where clinicians (for varied reasons) may refuse to acknowledge alternative ‘non-disease’ ways of understanding these experiences, such as those that draw on spiritual or religious narratives.

In either case, the clinical encounter (i.e, the consultation between mental healthcare professionals and patients) can become a “hermeneutical hotspot”. That is a location in social life “where a group’s unequal hermeneutical participation will tend to show up in a localised manner” (Fricker, p. 152). In this situation, rather than thinking about clinician and patient as two separate epistemic agents, I suggest that we also look at the role of the relational context (and the communicative dynamics) in mitigating or amplifying the hermeneutical hotspot created over time by certain cultural and clinical practices.

I suggest that correcting for hermeneutical injustice requires that both clinicians and patients engage in a form of hermeneutical humility and sincere attentiveness towards the person’s own subjectivity and situated meaning-making processes. As well as paying attention to psychopathological experiences linked with a certain mental health condition, clinicians should be alert to the ways in which contingent historical, autobiographical and social structures (such as colonialism, anti-Black racism, and heteropatriarchy) may shape the lived experience and meaning of such a condition.

I argue that critical phenomenology, intended as a praxis of freedom in seeking a deep transformative societal change, may help address hermeneutical marginalisation even within the limited confines of the clinical encounter. Adopting this stance requires the ability, on the part of the listener, to perceive the other as an expressive and trustworthy epistemic agent, even when their experiential world differs in fundamental ways from their reality (as in the case of psychosis). In these circumstances, rather than trying to avoid the epistemic asymmetry by labelling it as a “problem to be treated”, it may be more helpful to actively navigate and manage it with care, empathy and respect.

Popular posts from this blog

Delusions in the DSM 5

This post is by Lisa Bortolotti. How has the definition of delusions changed in the DSM 5? Here are some first impressions. In the DSM-IV (Glossary) delusions were defined as follows: Delusion. A false belief based on incorrect inference about external reality that is firmly sustained despite what almost everyone else believes and despite what constitutes incontrovertible and obvious proof or evidence to the contrary. The belief is not one ordinarily accepted by other members of the person's culture or subculture (e.g., it is not an article of religious faith). When a false belief involves a value judgment, it is regarded as a delusion only when the judgment is so extreme as to defy credibility.

Rationalization: Why your intelligence, vigilance and expertise probably don't protect you

Today's post is by Jonathan Ellis , Associate Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Center for Public Philosophy at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and Eric Schwitzgebel , Professor of Philosophy at the University of California, Riverside. This is the first in a two-part contribution on their paper "Rationalization in Moral and Philosophical thought" in Moral Inferences , eds. J. F. Bonnefon and B. Trémolière (Psychology Press, 2017). We’ve all been there. You’re arguing with someone – about politics, or a policy at work, or about whose turn it is to do the dishes – and they keep finding all kinds of self-serving justifications for their view. When one of their arguments is defeated, rather than rethinking their position they just leap to another argument, then maybe another. They’re rationalizing –coming up with convenient defenses for what they want to believe, rather than responding even-handedly to the points you're making. Yo

A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind

Today's post is by  Karen Yan (National Yang Ming Chiao Tung University) on her recent paper (co-authored with Chuan-Ya Liao), " A co-citation analysis of cross-disciplinarity in the empirically-informed philosophy of mind " ( Synthese 2023). Karen Yan What drives us to write this paper is our curiosity about what it means when philosophers of mind claim their works are informed by empirical evidence and how to assess this quality of empirically-informedness. Building on Knobe’s (2015) quantitative metaphilosophical analyses of empirically-informed philosophy of mind (EIPM), we investigated further how empirically-informed philosophers rely on empirical research and what metaphilosophical lessons to draw from our empirical results.  We utilize scientometric tools and categorization analysis to provide an empirically reliable description of EIPM. Our methodological novelty lies in integrating the co-citation analysis tool with the conceptual resources from the philosoph